Growing a Democratic Culture:
John Commons on the Wiring of Civil Society

Philip E. Agre
Department of Information Studies
University of California, Los Angeles
Los Angeles, California 90095-1520
USA

pagre@ucla.edu
http://polaris.gseis.ucla.edu/pagre/

This is a chapter in David Thorburn and Henry Jenkins, eds, Democracy and New Media, Cambridge: MIT Press, 2003.

Please do not quote from this version, which may differ in small ways from the version that appears in print.

2500 words.

 

Is the Internet a friend of democracy? One prevailing discourse says no, that the Internet is actually the end of democracy, and that it deprives all governments, democratic or not, of the ability to enforce their laws. Whatever its utility as political prescription, this libertarian philosophy has usefully directed attention to the complex and variegated institutional field through which the great bulk of any society is actually organized (e.g., Knight 1992, March and Olsen 1989, North 1990, Powell and DiMaggio 1991, Rosenau 1998). Marx had no time for these institutions of civil society, which he regarded as epiphenomena of class relations (Keane 1988). But the concept of civil society is now popular throughout the world and across the political spectrum (Keane 1998), whether as a counterbalance to the overreaching of the state, as an integral constituent of democracy, or as the real and only substance of a free society.

Yet the libertarian commitment to civil society is unstable. Civil society consists largely of intermediaries: organizations that orchestrate and subserve a wide variety of social relationships. But as Dominique Colas (1997) has observed, the concept of civil society did not enter European social thought as a liberal antidote to absolutism; its root meaning does not oppose it to the state. Rather, civil society was originally opposed to certain extreme forms of Protestantism that, in overthrowing the putative autocracy of the Church, also sought to destroy all intermediaries and all representations -- a mystical radicalism that sought to eliminate all obstacles to an unmediated communion with God. Political and technical ideas are routinely found to descend from secularized versions of medieval theology (Berman 1983, Lowith 1949, Noble 1997, Schmidt 1985 [1922], White 1978), and thus here the radicalism of modern libertarians echoes in some detail the origins of the concept of civil society -- not its supporters but its enemies: the smashers of idols, the extremist opponents of centralized authority, the militants seeking not to create their own intermediary institutions but to eliminate them altogether.

So it is, for example, that so many contemporary authors who seem to speak the libertarian language of Friedrich Hayek (1960) in fact leave no room in their language for government at all, not even the minimal constitutional framework that Hayek regarded as necessary to administer the rule of law. These libertarian enthusiasts are anarchists, and they are more concerned about the exercise of government power than about money laundering, or pedophiles, or any of the genuine if overhyped evils of the age. What matters most to them is the power of the network to connect anyone to anyone, to circumvent anything, to short-circuit any intermediary, and therefore supposedly to destroy all hierarchies of whatever sort (e.g., Gilder 1992). The state hierarchy, the monopoly -- all will be smashed, all destroyed, all of their atoms scattered by the ecstasy of the bits. This technological teleology, this electronic eschatology, is, we are given to understand, the information revolution to end all revolutions.

But it is not so. Nothing like that is happening. Intermediaries are changing, to be sure, multiplying and dividing, their functions rebundling into different configurations, but they are as necessary as ever (Sarkar, Butler, and Steinfield 1995; Spulber 1999). They are consolidating, indeed increasing their geographic scope (Casson 1997). States are not shrinking, and in fact they are compensating for the global reach of technology by creating a vast network of undemocratic and nontransparent global treaty organizations (Elazar 1998). Mediation and representation, with all of the good and evil that they imply, are the very essence of the age. Once we see this, we can see at last the real upshot of the technology, the real action that it has already set in motion. It is not the elimination of civil society, any more than of the state. It is, however, in both realms, the renegotiation of the working rules of every institution of society.

This conception of social institutions as sets of working rules that govern the roles and relationships of their participants belongs to John Commons (1924, 1934, 1970 [1950]). Commons was the mechanic philosopher of the New Deal. A printer, he eventually became a professor of economics at the University of Wisconsin, and in that position he trained many members of the generation that built the American welfare state. As the welfare state has come under assault, Commons has been nearly forgotten, mentioned only by a handful of legal theorists (e.g., Medema, Mercuro, and Samuels 1999) and institutional economists (e.g., Hodgson 1999). Although theories of institutional change vary greatly, most contemporary theories of institutions themselves are largely compatible with Commons' early formulation; they seem different on the surface because they all overgeneralize from the particular case with which the author is most familiar. Commons' theory started from his experience of the negotiation of work rules in printing shops through collective bargaining, and that was the paradigm that he brought to every institution he considered (1970 [1950]: 23-28). He did not imagine that every set of rules arises through the same formal mechanism by which union contracts are negotiated. He did not presuppose that organized associations of buyers and sellers will necessarily delegate representatives to negotiate over a long table the form contracts and other customary rules that govern a given industry at a given point in history. Nonetheless, Commons' project was to investigate the variety of mechanisms by which the stakeholder groups in a given institution do act collectively to carve out a space for their own customs and practices alongside and by compromise with those of everyone else.

Commons (1924) saw no better example of this process than the rise and evolution of the common law, in which successive social classes -- merchants at one point, industrialists at another, and then industrial labor -- wrote elements of their practices and values into the law as it emerged to govern the particular relationships of institutional life. How this worked in practice was a matter for investigation. Normatively, the point was not for any one group to win out, but quite the contrary for every group to be able to hold its own, neither imposing its complete set of preferred rules on everyone else nor having anyone else's rules completely imposed on them (1970 [1950]: 30-31).

As increasingly complex social relationships are mediated by networked information technology, we are becoming accustomed to the idea that the protocols of these mediated interactions -- the "code" in Lessig's (1999) terms -- constitutes a set of working rules in very much the sense that Commons suggests. Computers, like institutions generally, both enable and constrain, and both computers and institutions are, in one important aspect anyway, discourses made material -- made, that is, into machinery that governs to some degree the lives of the people who use it (Akrich 1992, Dutton 1999, Poster 1996, Reidenberg 1998). Even when they are not formally part of the government, and even when they have no legal force, institutions and computers both govern, and it is this larger sense of governance that Commons views as the deep underlying unity of democratic government and democratic society. It is unlikely that one can exist without the other, and if the Internet encourages a democratic society then it does so by promoting the diverse mechanisms of collective bargaining by which a democratic society orders its affairs.

The need for such mechanisms is clear. By providing a general mechanism for moving digital information and a general platform for constructing digital information utilities, the Internet provides new opportunities for the design of institutional mechanisms; it opens a vast new design space both for technology in the narrow sense and for the institutionalized social relationships within which the Internet is embedded. The Internet also necessitates a renegotiation of institutional rules in a more urgent way by destabilizing the balance of forces to which any successful negotiation gives form; by lending itself to the amplification of some forces and not others, the Internet undermines many of the institutionalized accommodations through which stakeholder groups with distinct interests and powers have gotten along.

It is not only the Internet that has such effects, of course; control over the legislature is a much more direct means of upsetting existing institutional arrangements, and more factors than information technology drive the disruptions of globalization. Nonetheless, the Internet, far from transporting its believers into the unmediated perfection of cyberspace, is unfreezing a multitude of thoroughly secular institutional arrangements right here on earth, and is posing the challenge of how these arrangements might be remade, both efficiently and equitably, in a more digital world.

Fortunately, what the Internet makes necessary it also makes possible. If the working rules of universities will be remade through a negotiation between professors and students, among others; if the medical system will be remade through a negotiation between physicians, patients, and insurers, among others; if the political system will be remade through a negotiation among citizens and their representatives, among others; then the Internet has provided tools that allow each of these stakeholder groups to associate and, each in its own way, to press its interests. Once again the paradigm of collective bargaining can mislead if it is taken too literally. The point is not that every social group forms its own union, or even necessarily its own organization, and the point is not that the Internet necessarily facilitates any kind of formal bargaining process. Collective bargaining can be mediated by a great diversity of institutional forms, and it is the genius of the Internet to be indifferent to the details of such things.

The Internet makes visible a layer of social process that is more fundamental than organizations, and just as fundamental as institutions, namely the customs by which people who have something in common think together (Agre 1998). Before collective bargaining comes collective cognition, and collective cognition in its various modes is greatly facilitated by the community-building mechanisms of the Internet. Ideologies can form in the networked community of computer programmers; news can spread in the networked community of nurses; experiences can be shared in the networked community of cancer patients; patterns can be noticed by the networked community of pilots; agendas can be compared by the networked community of environmental activists; ideas can be exchanged in the networked community of entrepreneurs; stories can be told within the networked community of parents; and so on.

This sort of cognitive pooling is not an unambiguous good, of course; if taken too far, it can turn each particular community into a weakened intellectual monoculture. Nonetheless, in many cases the Internet is amplifying collective cognition in ways that equalize playing fields for all. Cancer patients no longer need to confront the medical and insurance systems as individuals. Parents can listen to other parents who have been in their shoes. Small players can learn what angles the big players are likely to work. Collective cognition is not the same as collective action, much less formally organized collective bargaining. But it is the soil from which these more complex phenomena of solidarity grow. Without the habits of association, without the cultivated taste for sharing, without the concrete experience of helping others and being helped in turn, without the very idea that others face the same situation as you, a democratic culture cannot grow. Whatever its failings, the Internet fertilizes the soil of democratic culture.

The question, of course, is whether it does so enough -- whether the Internet provides the conditions for every social group, no matter how spread out, to take its rightful place at the table, to play its own role in renegotiating all of the social institutions in which it takes part. And the answer, just as clearly, is no. No technology is ever a sufficient condition for anything. It only facilitates. To truly build a democratic society, it will be necessary to build new social forms -- new ideas, new movements, and new organizations that are adequate the opportunities and challenges of a networked world.

The role of political organizations must change. An organization no longer needs to carry the full burden of organizing the collective cognition of the social group that it claims to represent. This is good when it frees resources for other purposes, and it is bad when it reduces the binding force that makes membership in an organization attractive in the first place. It is good when it reduces the arbitrary power of the intermediaries through whom the information had flowed, and it is bad when it makes consensus-building and leadership impossible. What, then, is the role of an organization in a networked world? An organization can place observers and advocates into complex forums like legislatures and standards bodies, where there is still no substitute for being there. It can conduct the research that requires pulling together more information than any individual could manage. It can maintain the relationships that make negotiations possible. And it can build the legitimacy that is required to call for a solidary action. These are all classical functions of an organization, and they will not go away. But they will all happen in a more dynamic environment, and they will only work if they draw upon and encourage the power of collective cognition, rather than trying to channel it. This is hard, because it is easier to deal with a centralized representative than a sprawling associative community. But it is the democratic way, and it is the principal hope today for a democratic society.

This perspective on democracy certainly has its limitations. Commons had a clear conception of institutions, but the language of collective bargaining was dangerously indeterminate in its prescriptions for the political system, as his misguided endorsement of Mussolini's corporate state (1970 [1950]: 33) suggests. But this is perhaps the central question of democracy in its newly wired manifestation: what is the proper relationship between collective cognition among communities of shared interest and the actual formal mechanisms of the state? Unequal access to the means of association is already a tremendous force for inequality, especially in the United States where professionalized lobbying on behalf of the powerful has been raised to a high art.

The answer cannot ride on the sort of bargaining that can be bought. Instead, it must ride on the massed creativity of a diverse people in diverse situations, all bringing their own experience to bear on the situations of others. If the Internet is a friend of democracy then democracy will be won principally on the ground, and a central task for democratic theory right now is to understand this ground, and to be useful to the innumerable people of good will who are out there trying to build on it.

Acknowledgements

I appreciate helpful comments by David Chess and Cosma Shalizi.

References

Philip E. Agre, Designing genres for new media, in Steven G. Jones, ed, CyberSociety 2.0: Revisiting CMC and Community, Newbury Park, CA: Sage, 1998.

Madeleine Akrich, The de-scription of technical objects, in Wiebe E. Bijker and John Law, eds, Shaping Technology/Building Society: Studies in Sociotechnical Change, Cambridge: MIT Press, 1992.

Harold J. Berman, Law and Revolution: The Formation of the Western Legal Tradition, Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1983.

Mark Casson, Information and Organization: A New Perspective on the Theory of the Firm, Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1997.

Dominique Colas, Civil Society and Fanaticism: Conjoined Histories, translated by Amy Jacobs, Stanford: Stanford University Press, 1997.

John R. Commons, Legal Foundations of Capitalism, New York: Macmillan, 1924.

John R. Commons, Institutional Economics: Its Place in Political Economy, Madison: University of Wisconsin Press, 1934.

John R. Commons, The Economics of Collective Action, Madison: University of Wisconsin Press, 1970. Originally published in 1950.

William Dutton, Society on the Line: Information Politics in the Digital Age, Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1999.

Daniel J. Elazar, Constitutionalizing Globalization: The Postmodern Revival of Confederal Arrangements, Rowman and Littlefield, 1998.

George Gilder, Life after Television, New York: Norton, 1992.

Geoffrey M. Hodgson, Economics and Utopia: Why the Learning Economy Is Not the End of History, London: Routledge, 1999.

John Keane, Civil Society: Old Images, New Visions, Stanford: Stanford University Press, 1998.

John Keane, Democracy and Civil Society: On the Predicaments of European Socialism, the Prospects for Democracy, and the Problem of Controlling Social and Political Power, London: Verso, 1988.

Lawrence Lessig, Code and Other Laws of Cyberspace, New York: Basic Books, 1999.

Karl Lowith, Meaning in History, Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1949.

Steven G. Medema, Nicholas Mercuro, and Warren J. Samuels, Institutional law and economics, in Boudewijn Bouckaert and Gerrit de Geest, eds, Encyclopedia of Law and Economics, Cheltenham, UK: Edward Elgar, 1999.

David F. Noble, The Religion of Technology: The Divinity of Man and the Spirit of Invention, New York: Knopf, 1997.

Friedrich A. Hayek, The Constitution of Liberty, Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1960.

Jack Knight, Institutions and Social Conflict, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1992.

James G. March and Johan P. Olsen, Rediscovering Institutions: The Organizational Basis of Politics, New York: Free Press, 1989.

Douglass C. North, Institutions, Institutional Change, and Economic Performance, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1990.

Mark Poster, Databases as discourse, or, Electronic interpellations, in David Lyon and Elia Zureik, eds, Computers, Surveillance, and Privacy, Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 1996.

Walter W. Powell and Paul J. DiMaggio, eds, The New Institutionalism in Organizational Analysis, Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1991.

Joel R. Reidenberg, Lex Informatica: The formulation of information policy rules through technology, Texas Law Review 76(3), 1998, pages 553-593.

James N. Rosenau, Governance and democracy in a globalizing world, in Daniele Archibugi, David Held and Martin Kohler, eds, Re-Imagining Political Community: Studies in Cosmopolitan Democracy, Stanford: Stanford University Press, 1998.

Mitra Barun Sarkar, Brian Butler, and Charles Steinfield, Intermediaries and cybermediaries: A continuing role for mediating players in the electronic marketplace, Journal of Computer-Mediated Communication 1(3), 1995.

Carl Schmitt, Political Theology: Four Chapters on the Concept of Sovereignty, translated by George Schwab, Cambridge: MIT Press, 1985. Originally publishing in German in 1922.

Daniel F. Spulber, Market Microstructure: Intermediaries and the Theory of the Firm, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1999.

Lynn White, Jr., Medieval Religion and Technology: Collected Essays, Berkeley: University of California Press, 1978.